After having studied Kimbrell's '7 Deadly Sins of Agriculture', there are truth, lies, and alternatives to be understood, sifted through, and organized. It is possible to make industrial food cheap, efficient and include the benefits of bio-tech. With the institution of education to the public on the dangers and hazards of industrial agriculture a better approach may be conceived. However, due to the large conglomerates monopolizing the industrial agriculture it is difficult for a small farmer to even make their own cheese legally because the kitchen that is required has strict constituents and is costly. By simply walking through your local supermarket it easy to see how many different food items include the same items (lots of corn syrup). Therefore education and attempts to manipulate biotech would prove futile and the cost of organic, locally grown food is high. Not only is industrial agriculture and GMO products 'killing' our children, but our landscape.
It has already been suggested by nature writers, conservationists and nature lovers everywhere that the best thing for the environment may be for everyone to go live in a selection of high rise, metropolitan areas; by concentrating all the pollution, and land degradation to one are it allows the rest of the natural world to flourish. So hey! why don't we just move all agriculture there as well?
Actually, attempts at "Urban Farms" have already been attempted. David Ferris from the Sierra Club writes about Ben Flanners, a New York local, who already sells to local markets, high end restaurants, and a third to customers who have subscribed to a local community supported agriculture club. If Flanners can do it and supply an adequate amount of people with food that is more healthy, readily accessible, and grown as naturally as possible, then why can't large scale agricultural projects be moved closer to the urban environment? Perhaps that's where the future of agriculture lies, maybe not, but it is one of the many possible alternatives - both for the land and our health.
Introduction to Philosophical Questioning
Monday, December 3, 2012
Is There Good Biotech?
We
recently read Andrew Kimbrell’s “Seven Deadly Myths of Industrial Agriculture.” His seventh myth is that “biotechnology will
solve the problems of industrial agriculture.”
According to Kimbrell, “New biotech crops will not solve industrial
agriculture’s problems, but will compound them.” He says, “Biotechnology will destroy
biodiversity and food security.” At the
end of the essay, he claims, “Biotechnology increases environmental degradation,
causes new food safety risks, and threatens to increase world hunger. It is not the solution, but a major part of
the problem.”
I
feel that Kimbrell is overly critical of biotechnology. He makes a blanket condemnation of all
biotechnology without exploring (or even considering) the possibility that biotechnology
could help the world in some ways. While
biotechnology does pose some dangers, which Kimbrell points out, it also has
the potential to benefit society. Not
all biotechnology is aimed at consolidating the power and increasing the profit
of multinational corporations. Some
biotechnology could do good for humanity, but it seems that Kimbrell wants to throw
all of it out the window. He rules out
any possibility that biotechnology could be beneficial. He comes across as being extreme and antitechnological.
Biotechnology,
for example, could be used to make certain foods more nutritious and better for
human consumption. Vitamin A deficiency,
for instance, causes hundreds of thousands of malnourished children to die and
go blind every year. Scientists, through
genetic engineering, have produced a new food known as golden rice, which
contains beta-carotene, a precursor to vitamin A. If grown and consumed in developing countries
where vitamin A deficiency is widespread, golden rice, a genetically modified
food, could put an end to many deaths and cases of blindness among children. Golden rice, the development of which has
been supported in part by the Bill and Melinda Gates Foundation, might go on
the market as early as next year. This
is just one example of how biotechnology could serve humanitarian purposes.
To
my objection, Kimbrell likely would reply that biotechnology can have
unintended consequences. For example, he
might argue that golden rice indirectly would lead to the destruction of other
kinds of rice or that golden rice might be harmful to nonhuman organisms. Golden rice, which is intended to end vitamin
A deficiency, could cause other problems.
It may, for example, lead to vitamin A overdoses if people consume too
much of it. An overabundance of vitamin
A in an individual’s system can lead to skin discoloration, hair loss, reduced
bone density, intracranial hypertension, liver damage, birth defects, and even
death. By trying to solve one problem
with biotechnology, humans unintentionally could create a whole new problem and
basically could end up poisoning the people whom they were trying to help. Kimbrell might suggest that we try to solve
problems of hunger and malnutrition through nontechnological means because they
are less risky. He might consider
biotechnology to be immoral and probably would recommend against playing
eugenics with our food.
Efficiency Issues
Kimbrell is completely against everything to do with industrial agriculture as we know it today. A major myth that Kimbrell addresses is the notion that industrial agriculture is the most efficient way to grow food. Kimbrell argues that industrial agriculture is in fact the opposite of efficient, but rather is completely inefficient. During the course of the reading, Kimbrell presents statistical data showing that smaller farms with less acres of land for growing crops can be from 2 up to 10 times more productive. Also presented is the fact that these so-called efficient farms leave a devastating effect on the environment. These bigger farms need more input as far as mechanically speaking as well as biochemically such as pesticides, etc. Through these two facts alone, industrial agriculture's efficient cover is blown.
However, a rebuttal to this view might be in what someone calls efficiency. Maybe the yield, or gain per crop is not the kind of efficiency we should be gauging. For example, while these larger farms may not be as efficient in the crops per plant, etc. but they are more efficient at bringing more food to the markets. The fact of the matter is that farming has become an expensive operation today, and less and less people are venturing into agriculture. If these large-scale corporate agricultural entities have the resources to bring in more crops than the average independent farmer due to more funding for machinery and chemicals, then why not let them? Perhaps the problem is not the efficiency, but the the major issue is the degradation to the environment. Perhaps new scientific discoveries can fix the loss of animal habitats and environmental degradation. Kimbrell would probably argue against this point of view to say that perhaps if the business was not so expensive to start up, then perhaps there would be far more independent farmers. Kimbrell would say that the industry politics today are heavily influenced by the major corporations. He would argue that more independent farmers would lead to the same amount of acres being planted with more yield.
However, a rebuttal to this view might be in what someone calls efficiency. Maybe the yield, or gain per crop is not the kind of efficiency we should be gauging. For example, while these larger farms may not be as efficient in the crops per plant, etc. but they are more efficient at bringing more food to the markets. The fact of the matter is that farming has become an expensive operation today, and less and less people are venturing into agriculture. If these large-scale corporate agricultural entities have the resources to bring in more crops than the average independent farmer due to more funding for machinery and chemicals, then why not let them? Perhaps the problem is not the efficiency, but the the major issue is the degradation to the environment. Perhaps new scientific discoveries can fix the loss of animal habitats and environmental degradation. Kimbrell would probably argue against this point of view to say that perhaps if the business was not so expensive to start up, then perhaps there would be far more independent farmers. Kimbrell would say that the industry politics today are heavily influenced by the major corporations. He would argue that more independent farmers would lead to the same amount of acres being planted with more yield.
Is Agrariansim the Best Answer?
In
Wendell Berry’s “The Whole Horse” he illustrates the stark differences between
agrarianism and industrialism and describes his perceived advantages of an agrarian
economy. Many of these aspects sound really desirable such as the benefits of a
close and personal local community and the extreme preservation of nearly all forests
and its inhabitants. The opposed economic system of industrialism is stated as
being one that is only concerned with “monetary capital” and that it only
generates “efforts to sell products for more than they are worth.” Given these
chosen descriptive characteristics it immediately becomes clear that one should
favor the former economic system to the latter. But when focusing on sound
economics, would a drastic overthrowing of the current economy into a farming
centered simplistic nineteenth century type system really be beneficial to all
people who compose our economy? There are, undoubtedly, some flaws in the
current “industrialist” system, there is another approach that could be taken
to reduce the negative impact of this system (particularly on the environment)
that would also achieve the agrarian principles of a more locally centered
society with an economy made up of many smaller businesses instead of a few
major corporations. The system I am referring to is free market capitalism.
Contrary to current popular belief, this proposed system is one that is far different from industrialism, in which large corporations lobby government to pass highly regulative legislation whose compliance costs and fees act to bar smaller firms from entering into the market. This atmosphere allows large corporations to go unchecked in the market and results in the monopolizing of many industries, particularly those whose products are more inelastic in demand. This setting of “crony capitalism” creates a ceiling above which no upcoming smaller firm can compete for market share with these massive favored corporations. This unholy alliance between government and corporations allows these large corporations to defy what would be the natural understood laws of the free market and behave irresponsibly in their operations with the understanding that they are indeed “too big to fail” and that any bankruptcy on the part of mismanagement will be covered through bailouts by the government. What consumers get as a result of this corrupt system are higher prices and lower quality in the goods bought, due to the absence competition among firms in the marketplace.
Contrary to current popular belief, this proposed system is one that is far different from industrialism, in which large corporations lobby government to pass highly regulative legislation whose compliance costs and fees act to bar smaller firms from entering into the market. This atmosphere allows large corporations to go unchecked in the market and results in the monopolizing of many industries, particularly those whose products are more inelastic in demand. This setting of “crony capitalism” creates a ceiling above which no upcoming smaller firm can compete for market share with these massive favored corporations. This unholy alliance between government and corporations allows these large corporations to defy what would be the natural understood laws of the free market and behave irresponsibly in their operations with the understanding that they are indeed “too big to fail” and that any bankruptcy on the part of mismanagement will be covered through bailouts by the government. What consumers get as a result of this corrupt system are higher prices and lower quality in the goods bought, due to the absence competition among firms in the marketplace.
With the
onset of market competition there would be more incentive for each individual
firm to control its own impact on the environment. Businesses are competitive
by nature and would welcome any opportunity to point out any shortcomings in a competitor’s
improper disposal of environmentally harmful waste and would certainly make an
effort to advertise their own unrivaled efforts of careful ecological
management, all in an effort to maximize market share and maintain an attractive
identity to customers.
The end
result may not offer the radical agrarian their ideal end, but a free market
economy that is unaltered by the influence of crony capitalism and large
corporate monopolies will produce a balanced effect that will allow for locally
driven economies to rely more on small and upcoming businesses instead of large
irresponsible corporations. The environment will not be relentlessly burdened
by the corporations who previously answered to no one. On the other hand,
technology will certainly become innovated at a higher rate and prices will
gradually decline. With the resulting lower market prices made possible through
a competitive market, households will have more disposable income. This
additional income will allow these families the agrarian opportunities of
developing their own desired means of sustenance and greater individual freedom
and self-reliance.
Sunday, December 2, 2012
The Fat Man Problem
I’ve been thinking a lot about this issue lately. The
question is if you would push one fat man off a bridge to stop a train that was
going to kill five people otherwise. Originally I said yes, because even though
every life has value, the numbers do matter. But then I changed my mind when I
heard about the wandering drifter problem. This is if you are a doctor trying
to save five people from dying. You need healthy organs in order to perform
surgery on them. Some drifter walks up and you have the opportunity to kill him
and use his organs. The situations seem different at first, but what it comes
down to is the fact that you are murdering that person rather than letting the
other five die.
The
only question I still ask myself though is if it is murder to let someone die
if you could stop it from happening. The best way to go about figuring this out
is to rearrange the situation. If you saw someone being held at gunpoint and
you had a button that would cause the attacker to pass out, would it be considered
murder to not press the button? Some say yes, but in reality, the man with the
gun is still committing the murder. Obviously, you feel morally obligated to
press the button to save that man, but you should never be alright with saving
someone at the expense of any number of people.
There
is also the question of what you should do and what you would do. These things
are far from being the same. For instance, if it was my relatives in place of
the five people on the tracks, then I would push the fat man off of the bridge.
I would do it, but I would feel horrible about it, because I know that it is
not what I should have done. Some people feel the opposite way. They feel that
if there were five random people on the tracks then they would feel obligated
to push the fat man. However, actually being in the moment is different, and
they would most likely end up not doing it.
One
more situation you can use is the trolley situation. This is where you have two
sets of tracks, one containing five random people, and the other containing one
person. The tracks are set for the train to hit the five people. You can pull a
lever that switches which track the trolley will take. When it comes down to
it, all you would be doing is manipulating the objects around you, and it
wouldn’t seem like you are actually murdering someone. But, when you think
about it, the Fat Man problem is the same exact concept, only you have to deal
with the fact that you are murdering the person up close. This is why I think
that I would not push the fat man onto the tracks. Even though I feel that five
lives are more valuable than one, I still think that you should not murder even
though it would save others.
Hunger and Industrial Agriculture
Andrew Kimbrell
argues in “Seven Myths of Industrial Agriculture” that industrial agriculture
will not feed the world. He points out that the mass enclosure of farms,
wrought by the domineering and ubiquitous food corporations, is a major reason
why hundreds of millions of people go hungry every day. Over the last century
in poor countries, first world corporations have fallen into the practice of ejecting
traditional peasants from their farmland in order to reap expensive, luxury
crops from the land. These crops, including cotton, coffee, and soybeans, are
immediately exported to rich countries. Nothing is left to feed the local poor.
The peasants, now without land on which to farm and sustain their families,
have no other choice but to move to urban areas to find menial labor. Forced
out of prosperous rural life, the growing class of urban poor is, as Kimbrell
puts it, “doomed to long-term hunger or starvation” because they have no means
with which to grow food for themselves.
Kimbrell continues
to argue that industrial agriculture is also afflicting current farmers with
hunger. As giant food conglomerates gain more and more control over small
farmers, they come to own the rights to everything that the farmers use,
including chemicals, seeds, and technology. This causes the farmers’ profits to
drop dramatically, forcing them into poverty.
Supporters of
industrial agriculture maintain that the people go hungry because not enough
food is produced to feed everyone in the world. They argue that the answer to
solving this problem is industrial agriculture, because industrial farms
produce a higher yield than low-tech farms. Increased industrial agriculture
would therefore increase the amount of food in the word, which would go toward
feeding the hungry. The only way to solve the problem of hunger, according to
some, is to increase industrialization in order to produce enough food to feed
the world’s bustling population.
Kimbrell argues
that this argument is flawed. He brings up evidence that proves that the
problem with hunger is not in the amount of food in the world. He states,
“Every year, enough wheat, rice, and other grains are produced to provide every
human with 3,500 calories a day.” The real problem, then, is clearly not with
the amount of food in the world. The most prevalent causes of hunger reside
within industrial agriculture itself, through the enclosure of farmland and the
oppression of small farmers.
Kimbrell states,
“hunger can only be solved by an agricultural system that promotes food
independence.” In pursuit of ending hunger, our generation must act quickly to
encourage food independence rather than sit by as disinterested food
corporations continue to increase hunger in the name of industrial agriculture.
The trolley problem
The trolley problem is set forth to inquire about peoples ethical
values when it comes to the life and death of others. The trolley problem goes
something like this; there is a runaway trolley careening down the track. In its
path there are four men, unaware of the trolley, working on the track, if the
trolley gets to them all will surly die. However on the track before the four
workers is a switch that will divert the trolley on to another set of tracks where
only one man works in its path. The question is; do you pull the switch or do
you just let the trolley run its course? Which is better or less bad, one
person to die or four people to die? In
the eyes of Mill the death of one person is the answer because it entails the overall
good for more people, or limits the overall pain and suffering to just one
person. For him it essentially is a numbers game. When people are asked what
they would do in this situation they almost always say that they would pull the
switch and cause only one person to die, however with a slight variation to the
scenario the answer changes.
In the
new scenario there is still a runaway trolley and four men in its path, however
this time the one person on the other track is not just some random stranger
but your own mother. Now what do you do? Do you pull the switch and kill your
own mother or do you just let the trolley run its course? When presented with
this scenario almost everyone would not pull the switch and save their own
mother. So is it ethical for us to value our mother’s life over someone else’s?
That random stranger in scenario one most likely has a family as well, so why
is your loss more important than theirs? In Mill’s opinion it shouldn’t matter
who the one person is on the other track, the right thing should still be to
save four people and let only one die because it limits the overall pain and
suffering to less people. However most people don’t have that same viewpoint
and this is why ethics can be such a difficult question to answer.
The Organ Transplant Problem
In “The Survival Lottery,” John
Harris puts forth the following scenario:
Suppose that organ transplant procedures have been perfected; that is to
say the only obstacle between a sick patient being saved and a doctor saving
them is the availability of the proper organs. Therefore, if the doctors are in
possession of the necessary organs required to save two dying patients, then we
can hold these doctors responsible for the lives of the patients. This means
that if the doctors allow the patients to die, we can say they died because their
doctors refused to treat them. However, if the doctors don’t possess the
necessary organs to save the two patients, then we would not be inclined to say
the doctors caused the patients’ deaths.
Further supposed that these two patients, A and B, are quite unhappy
about being left to die. A requires a new heart and B needs a new pair of lungs,
so they propose that if organs were harvested only from one healthy person, D, then two lives could be saved. The doctors
quickly jump to the obvious objection that it would be worse to kill one person
than to allow two to die. They would like to hold that we have an obligation not
to kill, but only a lesser duty of sorts to save life. A and B are not
satisfied with this response. While agreeing that an innocent life should never
be taken, they do not see how they are any less innocent than D; not one of the
three has done anything deserving of death. From here, A and B argue that if a
doctor refusing to treat a patient results in the patients’ death, then “he has
killed that patient as sure as shooting.” In this sense, A and B wish to equate
their own deaths with the forced death of D. If their premises hold true, then
I would be obliged to agree with them. A and B seem to think they’ve done a
splendid job thus far and move on to further objections and their proposal of a
Survival Lottery. I, however, do not think their argument thus far holds up.
First, if A and B needs organs urgent enough to consider the killing of
another person to save themselves, then surely one of them will be dead soon,
the organs from whom can be used to save the other. A and B would argue that
this creates a special group out of the sick, saying that we somehow discriminate
against them by only selecting donors from the sick. I, on the other hand,
think of it as a group of those that supports the notion that it is ok to kill
in order to preserve life. This form of their proposal lies rather close to
suicide, which I find much easier to justify than killing. A and B could also
object by saying that we are only saving one life in this manner instead of the
under their proposal. This would be rather sloppy of them, however, as it
forgets about D, who will be left alive.
There is also a problem with how A and B play with the notion and
treatment of innocents. They propose two premises in tandem that really only
work separately: that killing an innocent is universally wrong, and that if a
doctoring refusing to treat an innocent patient results in the patient’s death,
then the doctor killed the patient. The second premise can only come about if
the first premise isn’t present. If there truly were no other organs, not even
from other people, surely A and B would not blame death on the doctor. So in
the presence of other people, where are these organs supposed to come from if
killing innocent people is always wrong? A and B’s objections to killing
innocent civilians (those not in need of transplants) revolve around accusing
those making objections of avoiding the question. This is hardly fair as it
neglects the fact that there’s something wrong with their primary premises.
Perhaps, then, we should investigate their argument as if they had not
insisted that killing innocents is always wrong? This unfortunately leaves
without any solid motivation for treating A and B at all, with or without the
organs. Sure sometimes the doctors will use D’s organs to save A and B, but
other times they won’t. Something tells me A and B wouldn’t quite be satisfied
with this.
Harris, John. "The Survival Lottery." Pub. in Reason and Responsibility: Readings in Some Basic Problems of Philosophy. 637-641.
Thursday, November 29, 2012
The land of the abused and the home of the misused
“Fatal
Harvest” is a collection of essays from prominent ecological thinkers and
focuses on dispelling the disinformation that colossal “agribusiness” companies
have fed the American public since the early 70s. Unfortunately, it seems as though the
mentality of the early American pioneers of the 1800s still exists in the
contemporary world: the idea of man the conquer
of nature. The environmental
conservation movement did not begin in America until the early 20th
century, and was led by the renowned conservationists of the day: John Muir, Teddy Roosevelt, and Aldo Leopold
and many more. Aldo Leopold
revolutionized the way in which the average American viewed the environment through
his book “A Sand County Almanac.” Leopold
was in many ways ahead of his time, and contemporary readers still cite his
book when faced with the large amount of destruction made by Industrialized
Agriculture. For example, “We abuse land
because we see it as a commodity belonging to us. When we see land as a
community to which we belong, we may begin to use it with love and respect.” However, industrialized agriculture has
obviously not read his book and continue to muck up the environment as “man the
conquer.” They lace their good-intentioned
goals with counterproductive measures that only serve to increase prices and
scar the environment all so the maximum profit can be achieved.
One particular
set of essays in “Fatal Harvest” tells of the “Seven Deadly Myths of Industrial
Agriculture,” and the fifth myth is that “Industrial food offers more choices.” Although this is a tactic used by the
gigantic “Agribusiness” in order to promote its agenda, this idea is simply a
grand fabrication. The truth of the
matter is quite alarming because, according to the U.N. Food and Agricultural Organization
(FAO), “we have lost nearly 93 percent of lettuce, over 96 percent of sweet
corn, about 95 percent of tomatoes, and almost 98 percent of asparagus varieties.” From a biological standpoint, these numbers
are horrifying. The higher amount of given
variation a population of organisms have (plants or animals), the better
adapted that those organisms will be in the face of a new disease
developing. Periodically in history, certain
biological events occur that favor a type of bacteria to explode in prevalence;
the only manner in which the organisms on this planet are able to survive such
catastrophic epidemics is through the complex machinery of our genetic
diversity. When the genetic diversity is
decreased to such levels that have already happened then that is a recipe for
disaster because all it would take for a mass crop failure to occur would be for
a deadly bacterium to develop and mutate to the point to where we are unable to
stop it before it completely decimates our food supply. I feel as though so many people have tried to
extract as much wealth as possible from the American system without regard for
any of the negative ramifications that could follow and now we are spiraling
out of control into a nosedive towards the ground. Even as horrible as it is to say, I feel that
the only way in which we will change our collective societal mind will be after
a major catastrophe occurs; the type of tragedy that will be written in the
history books as the day in which our ignorance of the environment finally came
back to haunt us. Mother Nature’s vengeance
shall come back in full fury, and people of like mind to John Muir and Aldo
Leopold will only be there to witness the destruction that they have foreseen
for decades.
Andrew Kimbrell (Ed.). Fatal
Harvest: The Tragedy of Industrial
Agriculture. Washington DC: Island
Press, 2002.
Wednesday, November 28, 2012
Value Objectivist with a Twist
As discussed in Palmers “An
Overview of environmental ethics”, Value objectivists believe that value is not
something that humans create, yet something that already existing in the
world. One concern however is the
question of what actually is of intrinsic value. Palmer suggested the ability for something to flourish
seemed reasonable. I believe
however, that value can be found deeper within things.
The
value of an earthly thing, no matter living or not is relative to that things
ability to conduct, convert or exchange energy. The entire planet is one biosphere, which is continuously
cycling its resources within itself, and for itself. The unifying quality that functions throughout all things is
energy, and each specific way that it passes energy.
Energy is the very reason why human beings consume our
breakfast lunch and dinner, and the same reason why birds eat seeds, lions eat antelope,
plants need sun, because every living thing has energy level (value if you will),
which is as unique as each thing itself.
Living things need energy to live, and receive and transfer it to
themselves, all metabolizing differently, at different speeds and rhythms.
To
judge the value of something one would judge the energy qualities of something,
and how useful the energy level it contains, the energy transfers it can
perform or simply it conducting qualities. All things on this earth manipulate energy and this very
energy has value or importance to the energy-consuming organisms around. Animals will eat the healthiest looking
crop in the forest; trees can grow up and out of a permanently shaded place to
reach light, and human beings use energy in every way possible. Energy is constantly moving throughout
all things within this biosphere and is necessary to sustain life, can be
passed indirectly through non-living things. It can be held, used, transferred.
It
seems instinctual to value what sustains, drives and provides for all life.
And yes florishing needs energy, but energy doesn’t always
cause flourishing, but always cause cycling.
Tuesday, November 27, 2012
The Ethics of Professional Football and Brain Injuries
According to a study conducted in 2000, 60% of professional football players have had at least one concussion and 26% have had three or more. Players who have sustained a concussion are three times more likely to develop symptoms of depression and are 73% more likely to develop Parkinson's disease. However, when delivered these facts, most professional football players are remiss. ESPN the Magazine conducted a poll in 2011 that found 64% of professional football players would take 10 years off of their life in exchange for a super bowl MVP. Why are these players not concerned about the consequences of their incredibly violent and dangerous sport? Should the National Football League Player's Associations (NFLPA), which is in charge of protecting players' rights, intervene in order to make this game safer and to force the league to assist former players with their medical bills, which are almost universal? The answer seems very obvious to an outside observer, but the players are deeply divided on the issue.
Offensive players are much more likely to support rule changes that would reduce the likelihood of brain injuries because it would have a limited impact on their playing style. In fact, the rules would often force defenses to play a more lax coverage - giving receivers, for example, a competitive advantage. Also, quarterbacks and kickers would benefit from the rule changes because it would reduce the aggression that defenders would legally be allowed to use on them. However, defensive players strongly oppose the rules because studies show that they are just as likely to sustain a brain injury, but rule changes would dramatically change their style of play. Forcing them to hesitate before making a tackle and to make sure they properly executed their tackle when they were allowed to do so. It is important to remember that defensive players have played according to a certain set of rules for their entire football careers, from ages 7 until around 32, without and change. To introduce new rules would change the dynamic of the game and could, potentially, take away the livelihood of these players, who have no other backup careers.
As lamentable as it as, there is simply no choice in this matter. The NFL must institute rules to protect players. The game of professional football has become progressively more dangerous as players have become faster and stronger over the years. It is time for the only governing body with and influence, the NFL, to step in and save these players for making the decision between life and football.
Offensive players are much more likely to support rule changes that would reduce the likelihood of brain injuries because it would have a limited impact on their playing style. In fact, the rules would often force defenses to play a more lax coverage - giving receivers, for example, a competitive advantage. Also, quarterbacks and kickers would benefit from the rule changes because it would reduce the aggression that defenders would legally be allowed to use on them. However, defensive players strongly oppose the rules because studies show that they are just as likely to sustain a brain injury, but rule changes would dramatically change their style of play. Forcing them to hesitate before making a tackle and to make sure they properly executed their tackle when they were allowed to do so. It is important to remember that defensive players have played according to a certain set of rules for their entire football careers, from ages 7 until around 32, without and change. To introduce new rules would change the dynamic of the game and could, potentially, take away the livelihood of these players, who have no other backup careers.
As lamentable as it as, there is simply no choice in this matter. The NFL must institute rules to protect players. The game of professional football has become progressively more dangerous as players have become faster and stronger over the years. It is time for the only governing body with and influence, the NFL, to step in and save these players for making the decision between life and football.
Subjectivity/Objectivity and the Environment
In Clare Palmer’s “An
Overview of Environmental Ethics,” she highlights various central questions; in
particular, the value of certain components of the environment.
Palmer addresses two
variations of value: instrumental value, or value that can be used as a means
to an end, and non-instrumental (intrinsic) value, which is value that is, in
itself, an end.
These varying definitions
of value result in a dispute between value subjectivists and value
objectivists. As a subjectivist, value is something that we create and assign
to our lives. As an objectivist, value is something that already exists in the
world, independent of our existence.
The example used in the
text was water: water is seen as an instrumental value to humans, for it is
used to keep us alive, therefore making it a means to an end. It is valued
because it is necessary for us. Palmer states that “water…is of instrumental
value to humans because it helps in achieving another goal – that is, remaining
alive.” But what about for all of the people in other countries who do not have
access to clean water? For them, drinking water would be detrimental to their
health and, ultimately, their lives. The quality of the water does not change
the fact that they need it to live, but it does change the value of it: water
is no longer a means to an end (living), but an end in itself (sickness or
death).
I believe that all aspects
of the environment should be seen objectively. It should not matter that they
do not directly or indirectly aid us. For those with clean water to drink, we
are often not concerned with those who don’t have clean water, because we view
the environment subjectively; if it doesn’t affect us, why should we really
care? But if it were viewed in an objective way, the preservation of clean
water (and on the large scale, the environment) would be the end in itself, and
it wouldn’t matter which people (and ultimately, countries and continents),
benefitted, because we would be doing it in for the sake of the environment.
The Golden Rule - Not So Simple
The golden rule is one of the most
basic and universal concepts: “do unto others as you would be done by them”.
This idea is present in some form in most cultures. Although it is often stated
that it was originally a Christian teaching, similar principles occur in
Confucianism, Buddhism, Hinduism, Taoism, and Judaism before Jesus’s time.
Influence of the golden rule can be found in most ethic systems as well.
Utilitarianism focuses on achieving the greatest amount of happiness for the
greatest amount of people.
Mill said that he thought utilitarianism to be
an improvement on the golden rule, which he thought selfishly ignored the
collective happiness of the community for individuals’ needs. However, true
utilitarianism can easily result in ignoring minorities, while the following
the golden rule works on specific instances, preventing sacrifice for the
‘greater good’. Kant felt that he too was improving the golden rule with
categorical imperative. The two concepts are similar – followers of both would
agree that if there is something you would not want done to you, then you
should not do it.
Kant would expand this argument to
universalize the judgment as a maxim, and say that no one should do the action
in question. This condition aims to prevent any problems that would arise from
differences of taste. The example George Bernard Shaw gives is that a sadist or
a masochist would personally enjoy causing or receiving pain, and according to
the golden rule would be justified in hurting others. Religiously following the
categorical imperative can also result in consequences not thought to be moral.
The golden rule is said to be ‘empirical’ in how it is used to judge
situations, while Kant’s rule is binding. If someone was hiding Jews from the
Nazis, by the universalization of lying being bad, they would be forced to
reveal the Jews when confronted, while under the golden rule they would not
because they would not want to be exposed if they were the ones hiding.
While utilitarianism and
deontology have specific similarities and differences to the golden rule,
virtue does not because of its approach to ethics, as its focus is on the
character of the individual making the decisions rather than the individual
him/herself. This being said, those concerned with morals first would certainly
consider the golden rule to be a good base for judgments because it requires
empathy and compassion.
As popular as it is, the golden
rule in its most frequent form is not perfect. William T. Vollmann reflects on
the variations of the golden rule in the ‘Moral Calculus’ chapter of his book, Rising Up and Rising Down. The most
pressing issue is that it could be interpreted into what he calls the zealot’s
golden rule: “do unto others as you are doing for yourself”; another
formulation would be the so-called missionary’s golden rule: “do unto others as
you convince yourself they would be done by.” According to these
extrapolations, a Christian could be justified in forcing others to convert
because it is as they would want. These variations are the cultivation of what
hesitations Kant and Shaw had about the golden rule. In response, Vollmann
offers the empath’s golden rule: “do unto others, not only as you would be done
by, but also as they would be done by. In case of variance, do the more
generous thing.” His expansion eliminates the problems of the original form,
but requires knowledge that may not always be available. However, it still
improves the initial maxim.
There also has been much debate
about whether the positive (do unto others….) or negative (do not do unto
others) form of the golden rule is superior; the first is more popular in
Western society as it is the Christian form, but the latter is much more
widespread. The problem translates the same using the empath’s variation or the
original. The implications of the negative version are that it only provides
guidance in what not to do, not what one should do. It focuses on preventing
negative action, while the positive form gives motivation toward positive
action, which would bring more good into the world.
Subscribe to:
Posts (Atom)