The idea that the argument for free will and separation of mind and body are completely independent of each other is not all that absurd. When examined closer the premise can be that the idea of physicalism can be intertwined with the argument for hard-determinism. Inversely, the thought that dualism and libertarianism are proponents of each other can also be argued for. Separation of the mind and body makes all the difference between barrier of acting according to natural laws and causal events or instigation of said events through agent causation in the brain.
Lets look at the idea of physicalism and hard-determinism. A steadfast hard-determinist such as Hume argues for the logical process of event-causality; that is to say a stream events influences the apparent 'choice' of the an intelligent being. When acting within natural laws the phsyiological contingencies provide easier clarification of sequence of events. One example in the identity theory, that mental states are identical to physical states (pain and the stimulation of c-fibers). By comparing folk psychology to a scientific psychology it is apparent that through a scientific psychology and understand of the brain we can determinedly predict the actions of a human through their traits, desires, habits, etc. via a complete understanding of the neurological processes and union of mind and body. As suggested, if a child is a raised to understand these physiological and mental processes at a complete neuro-scientific level the child would be able to predict the 'decisions' of another human eliminating any hint that the person had a choice of will.
This was instituted in the idea of "Mary Don't Know". Living in a black and white room being taught all the physical knowledge of colour, a similar understanding would allow us to predict Mary's reactions to the colour green when observed for the first time; Mary herself, would know what to expect.
However, there is the objection that knowledge is intentional. Complete physical knowledge is a different kind of knowledge. Physical knowledge is factual, where as Mary upon experiencing green for the first time gains a knew type of knowledge, both competent and acquaintance knowledge. This new light shows that there is an equivocation of knowledge, and further more that her experience is something new and felt inherently, causing her decisions to be determined internally as to how she reacts to colours. Her decision how to react cannot be predicted as it is a proponent of agent-causation (immanent causation according to Chisholm). By acting of her own accord despite the series of events reinforces her mind-body duality; her consciousness is related to non-physical properties - The Qualia Problem (as according Jackson). Ergo, the divide between the Dualism argument and the Free Will argument is not as big as expected, while the ties may be vast, the correlation is definitely apparent.
Friday, September 21, 2012
Active and Passive Euthanasia
In
Active and Passive Euthanasia (pg. 641-645 of our text), James Rachels argues
that passive and negative euthanasia are morally equivalent actions. He begins with
a simple statement that physicians, and most people, in most cases find nothing
morally reprehensible in allowing a suffering patient to die. However, as
decreed by the House of Delegates of the American Medical Association, “the
intentional termination of the life of one human being by another – mercy killing
– is contrary to that for which the medical profession stands...” It is against
this claim that Rachels argues.
One of
the simplest situations where this topic would find relevance is in the case of
a terminally ill patient with merely days left to live but whose pain cannot be
alleviated. The patient does not want continue living through those days in
intense agony, so he asks the doctor to end his life. The doctor can make one
of two choices: euthanize the patient (active), or cease treatment and allow
him to die (passive). If the doctor euthanizes the patient, then the patient’s
suffering ends immediately. If the doctor chooses the latter option, then the
patient will day perhaps a few days earlier than if the ineffective treatment had
been continued. If these two options are all that remain, then the doctor has
already decided that alleviating the patients suffering has surpassed in
importance even the patient’s life. With this in mind, isn’t merely ceasing to
treat the patient contrary to this other choice the doctor has already made?
Rachel thinks so, as do I.
One
reason many people are opposed to active euthanasia is the bias that people
have towards killing. Rachels brings up that this is mostly attributable to the
situations in which killing and allowing to die are commonly compared. People
find it very easy to imagine terrible situations involving killing; murders and
wars surround us continually. But outside of the medical field being discussed
here, people rarely hear of others being allowed to die. However, it is the
nature of these acts that differentiates them morally, not how often they
occur. A serial killer is motivated by greed, or anger or one of many other
self-serving negative emotions and desires. The doctor, on the other hand, is
understood to be acting with humanitarian goals in mind. Because we are so
focused on the context of the acts, we forget that it is really the motivations
behind them that we are judging. And if motivation and purpose are how the
morality of acts can be distinguished, then active euthanasia is equivalent to
passive euthanasia.
Some might wrongly try to attribute
the cause of death to the disease itself, saying that if the cancer was the
cause of sickness, then cancer is what caused the patient to die, not the
inaction of the doctor. Therefor the doctor is not morally responsible. This
can be tackled in many ways. Rachels uses the argument that when morally
speaking, one cannot not act. Even choosing to do nothing is a moral action.
Therefor you are responsible for whatever happens after the doctor’s ceased
treatment. With this in mind, I would go back to a previous argument as further
evidence. In this case the doctor is still making the same decision as before,
that allowing suffering to end is more morally noble than prolonging a life of
pain. If both these arguments are true, then not wanting to be the cause of
someone’s death is not a valid standpoint.
From
the arguments presented, I can see no convincing argument morally differentiating
active and passive euthanasia. So the real discussion then becomes whether or
not euthanasia of any form is just, be it by suicide, doctor’s assistance, etc.
The choice is truly about the value of life. In any relevant circumstance,
continuing treatment in an attempt to preserve life and active euthanasia in
order to immediately end suffering are the only valid options. Passive
euthanasia is in fact the worst possible choice because not only does it allow
suffering to exist, but it is also dishonest.
Thursday, September 20, 2012
What is love?
Suppose a writer want to write a
love story. They loved the concept
of romance and found it extremely heart warming. However they had never actually been in a loving
relationship. The writer had read
or watched endless quantities of romantic comedies and dramas, observed loved
ones and asked questions about their relationship. From all of the information they had gathered, the writer
felt as if they had come to realize the true nature of love. The writer was able to obtain all
physical information possible on the topic, yet they had never actually fallen
in love. Is he or she really able
to claim that they understand love?
Can a major league football coach able to play football? The Platonic philosophy claims that
only some subjects are permitted to claim that they understand the true meaning
of love. The Platonic philosophy
behind love is seemingly the most accurate compared to any other theory
pertaining to love.
So,
what is love? Plato defended the Greek theory of Eros, which states one strives
for beauty. One is able to find
beauty through a person, a hobby, idea, etc. and by discovering this particular
beauty, one is able to find true beauty in the world. The reason why Eros is such a precise definition is because
it claims that love is both physical and mental. There are theories that love is just strictly physical. The reasoning why one may love another
is only for mating reasons.
Another example is a mother who cares for her child. Without that caring quality, the infant
will most likely die without the constant acknowledgment and love from its
mother. For mating, without the
desire to mate with another species, there would be no children. This desire is a key element to Eros. The strive for beauty, which could be
through mating or taking care of a child, is a necessary quality for every
species. The mentality aspect of
Eros is technically the proper form of love. Although the physical quality is necessary, love is the
exploration or reflection of an idea, which develops into the pursuit of true
or ideal beauty.
One
of the major questions that I have pondered is whether or not love is
rational. I truly believe that
love exists but does it have any rationality. After learning more about the philosophy of love, I believe
that love is very rational. The
reason why it may appear irrational is due to how people act while in
love. Without love there would be
no thrive for anything really. We
do the things we do because we enjoy doing them for the most part. We love because we find beauty in the
things we love and enjoy doing. As
stated before, love is a necessary quality to keep children alive and to
mate. The idea that people do
irrational things while they are in love is actually perfectly rational. Although some people may commit extreme
acts to present their love for another, to them, they think that they are
acting in a rational manner in order to keep their love thriving. I am not agreeing with stalking or any
other poor ways of presenting love, but I can say that what they think they are
doing is rational. Love is a
beautiful, necessary and rational quality in which I am glad to have the
ability feeling.
What is Real?
A
much discussed topic in philosophy is the idea of what “real” is. To me, I
think that people look too far into this topic. The concept of “real” isn’t
something that actually exists. Real is just a word defined by humans to
represent all of the things that humans are able to perceive with their senses.
Real is also a relative term. I can’t tell you how many times I’ve heard people
say, “Well how do we know if what we are experiencing is the real reality?”
This is absurd! What we see, feel, touch, hear, and smell is real because that
is all we can conceive is to be true. Maybe there is more than what exists in
the universe, but these things would be in completely different reality. So I’d
say that some of the arguments in are a bit pointless.
There
is all this talk in the book about examining things that are possible and
impossible. What is the point of examining things like this? There are just two
categories: real and unreal. The “squircle” is considered to be in the impossible
section in the book and a unicorn is something that is considered possible.
Both of these things are just unreal, and that’s all it amounts to. It’s kind
of like when people say there is a sixty percent chance of rain. The reality is
that there is always a fifty percent chance of rain. Either it will or it won’t.
Likewise, things are either real or unreal. That’s it!
I
was actually just getting into a discussion with people in my dorm lobby about
the topics dreams and alternate realities. When it comes to dreams, everyone
surprisingly agreed with me in saying that dreams are actually a reality. All
we experience during the day is just perception from our mind. Dreams are the
same way; you just don’t have to rely on your senses. Also, Gabriel Elders
asked me, “If this was all a simulation, would this be real?” I would have to
say that yes, it would be real……real to us. That is not denying the fact that
there would be another reality outside of this one. It is just that the one
outside of ours is something that we can’t perceive at the moment. Therefore it
is not real to us.
So,
I know that this isn’t a popular opinion among philosophers because it is too
simplistic. But life is as simplistic as you want to make it. When you’re looking
at a concept like “real,” it all comes down to the fact that it is a concept
that we formulated into a word to make it seem like the concept itself exists
in itself. But the fact of the matter is it doesn’t exists, we only think it
does, because we can comprehend the idea. So, I guess my final thought on the
matter is that “reality” is a concept which exists as only an idea and is
determined by what we perceive.
My Qualia Problem
The argument of Mind-Body dualism fascinates me. Separate or the same? There are countless arguments for and against either side, but I tend to find myself a dualist thinker. I switched to this side of the argument, surprisingly as I am a big proponent of science having an explanation for everything. Frank Jackson's The Qualia Problem was influential in my thinking that the mind is separate from the body, and I will now do my best to give a quick recap of the argument.
The main point of the argument is that there are some experiences, despite having all knowledge and physical descriptions, definitions, etc., that cannot be completely be described as knowledge just from a physical aspect. The argument goes on to give two very clear-cut examples of how this can be true. Both examples use the sense of vision in humans. The first example uses an individual, "Fred" with an extraordinary ability to distinguish two types of red coloring in objects in which no other human can see. We might have all of the physical knowledge of the process of how sight happens from cones and rods to the brain but we still cannot know what seeing these two colors would be like. This actual experience would bring about a new understanding of what Fred was going through. This new perception could be nothing more than new knowledge, which physicalism alone cannot explain.
Now there would be some who would argue this point, fair enough. Most would attack the qualia argument through the concept of knowledge. For instance, the gaining of the incredible new sight Fred had would not be considered new at all, but rather a sort of affirmation of the physical knowledge already obtained.
However, Jackson would probably argue that this reaffirmation is a little too in depth. Simply put, to me, a new experience such as seeing a new color would definitely be new knowledge as opposed to an update on already understood information. The qualia argument just hits so home to me, being as clever as it is, in that I can relate to instances in which a new experience could not be explained by physical means alone. I could be told how the feeling of euphoria comes about in the brain and have all leading scientists tell me about how winning an NBA championship game would bring about this feeling, but there would be nothing like experiencing that actual winning of the NBA championship. I can't help but think I would learn something new that cannot be explained by physical means alone.
The main point of the argument is that there are some experiences, despite having all knowledge and physical descriptions, definitions, etc., that cannot be completely be described as knowledge just from a physical aspect. The argument goes on to give two very clear-cut examples of how this can be true. Both examples use the sense of vision in humans. The first example uses an individual, "Fred" with an extraordinary ability to distinguish two types of red coloring in objects in which no other human can see. We might have all of the physical knowledge of the process of how sight happens from cones and rods to the brain but we still cannot know what seeing these two colors would be like. This actual experience would bring about a new understanding of what Fred was going through. This new perception could be nothing more than new knowledge, which physicalism alone cannot explain.
Now there would be some who would argue this point, fair enough. Most would attack the qualia argument through the concept of knowledge. For instance, the gaining of the incredible new sight Fred had would not be considered new at all, but rather a sort of affirmation of the physical knowledge already obtained.
However, Jackson would probably argue that this reaffirmation is a little too in depth. Simply put, to me, a new experience such as seeing a new color would definitely be new knowledge as opposed to an update on already understood information. The qualia argument just hits so home to me, being as clever as it is, in that I can relate to instances in which a new experience could not be explained by physical means alone. I could be told how the feeling of euphoria comes about in the brain and have all leading scientists tell me about how winning an NBA championship game would bring about this feeling, but there would be nothing like experiencing that actual winning of the NBA championship. I can't help but think I would learn something new that cannot be explained by physical means alone.
On Gertler's Argument
I find Gertler's argument for dualism to be sound. I should state as a preamble that I am perhaps a little biased, as I have believed in dualism since before I knew the word dualism. It has always been my way of coping with pain, both physical and emotional. I can handle pains I experience effectively by setting my mind apart from my body, believing that events such as stubbing my toe, splitting my head open, and even depression are simply caused by events pertaining to my body, but not necessarily to my mind, or soul. My faith is that there is something greater behind we human beings, something that not even science can hope to explain, that makes our lives worth living in this world riddled with suffering. Thus, I immediately find arguments that defend mind-body dualism, such as Gertler's argument, to be appealing.
I will do my best to summarize Gertler's argument for mind-body dualism: If we can conceive of an event, than it the event is possible. If two things are necessarily equal, than it would be impossible to conceive of one existing without the other. For example, we cannot conceive of water existing without H2O, and vice versa. Therefore, water = H2O. Physicalists believe that the mind is necessarily equal to the body. However, there are some cases in which we can conceive of the mind as being disembodied, or separate from the body. For example, we can conceive of ourselves experiencing pain while we are not actually experiencing that pain in our bodies. Thus, the mind is not necessarily equal to the body, and dualism is true.
After much rumination on Gertler's argument, I realized that it corresponds with my own justification for my belief in dualism. I can certainly conceive of my mind existing without the presence of my body. Through meditation I can imagine my mind, or soul, observing my physical body from the outside. Thus, my mind is not necessarily equal to my body.
However, there is one objection to Gertler's argument that keeps nagging me. While we have proven that the mind is not necessarily equal to the body, we have perhaps not proven that the mind and the body are completely separate. What if the mind is contained inside of the brain, so that it is not necessarily the same as the brain, but it still could not exist without it? As far as I can see, Gertler does not provide a rebuttal to this objection. If you, the reader, have an opinion concerning this objection, whether it is for or against it, I would love to hear it!
- Adam Nick
Wednesday, September 19, 2012
The Self-Immolation of Duc
On June 10, 1963, South Vietnam is a
month into the Buddhist Crisis. The
government of President Ngo Dinh Diem is committing actions that restrict free
religious practice by the country’s Buddhist majority. In response, there has been a large movement
of civil resistance and protest, led primarily by Buddhist monks and nuns,
against the government and its repressive, anti-Buddhist policies.
Blocks away from the Presidential Palace,
a crowd gathers around a group of some 350 monks and nuns, who plan to demonstrate
against the South Vietnamese government.
A monk by the name of Thich Quang Duc and two other monks emerge from a
car in the middle of the procession. A
circle has formed around them.
One monk places a cushion in the middle
of the road; and Duc, prayer beads in hand, seats himself in the lotus
position. Duc, prior to this demonstration,
has written a letter, in which he “respectfully plead[s] to President Ngo Dinh
Diem to take a mind of compassion towards the people of the nation and
implement religious equality to maintain the strength of the homeland eternally.”
In the middle of the road,
Duc continues to sit calmly while the second monk pours on him gallons of
gasoline. Duc lights a match and then
drops it onto himself.
David Halberstam of The New York Times wrote:
I was to see that sight again, but once was enough. Flames were coming from a human being; his body was slowly withering and shriveling up, his head blackening and charring. In the air was the smell of burning human flesh; human beings burn surprisingly quickly. Behind me I could hear the sobbing of the Vietnamese who were now gathering. I was too shocked to cry, too confused to take notes or ask questions, too bewildered to even think ... As he burned he never moved a muscle, never uttered a sound, his outward composure in sharp contrast to the wailing people around him.
This form of suicide, usually done
in protest, is known as self-immolation.
In the article “In Defense of
Mind-Body Dualism,” Brie Gertler puts forward her Disembodiment Argument. According the argument, the identity theory
of physicalists is false because it is supposedly conceivable and, therefore,
possible for pain to be felt while disembodied.
I do not find her argument to be
convincing because I do not believe that it is reasonable to appeal to
disembodiment. How can we ever have a “sufficiently
comprehensive” concept of disembodiment if none of us has ever had the experience of being disembodied?
Instead, I believe that identity
theory can be disproved by looking at events that actually have happened and have been observed. According to the identity theorist, mental states
are identical to particular physical states.
This applies universally.
From this, I believe that it is
reasonable to say that the physical state of being on fire will, under the
identity theory, be identical to, in all people, a mental state of extreme
pain. Who on fire would not experience
extreme pain? The identity theorist probably
would argue that being on fire causes in the nervous system extreme pain, which
the individual experiences in the mind, which is part of the body.
When looking at purported laws that
are supposed to apply universally, one should look at extreme cases to see if
the theory or hypothesis holds up under all
circumstances.
The identity theory, in my opinion,
is disproved by the self-immolation of Thich Quang Duc. Fire causes a person extreme pain, and
extreme pain causes a person to react.
Duc did not react when he was on fire.
As far as I see it, it is impossible for a person not to react to being
on fire, unless that person has separated his consciousness from his body. If the mind and the body are separable, then
the identity theory is false and dualism must be true.
In other words:
1) Being on fire causes the nervous
system to send to the brain signals that should trigger pain if the identity
theory is true. The pain that is caused by being on fire is so intense that a person’s body involuntarily will react if the identity theory is true.
2) It is impossible for a person
not to react to being on fire if the identity theory is true because the nervous
system signals being sent to the brain, which is physical, would be identical to
the pain that should be felt by the mind, which is part of the body.
3) The only possible way to avoid
such signals caused by fire from causing pain would be to separate consciousness from
the body.
4) Thich Quang Duc did not react at all to
being on fire; therefore, to endure being on fire, he must have, through meditation or some other
method, separated his mind from his body.
C) Therefore, the
identity theory is false. Since the mind
and body can be separated, dualism must be true.
The de facto First Lady of South Vietnam offered what I believe to be the only rational objection that an identity theorist could make in response to Duc not responding to being on fire:
Madame Nhu argued that Duc must have
been intoxicated, which is why he did not respond to being on fire. Whether any level of intoxication could
prevent someone whose mind and body are identical from responding to being burned alive, I will let you be the
judge.
Are We Free?
Are
we really free to make choices? This question had come to my mind a few times
in my life but I had never really given any serious thought to it. I had always
just had the belief that I was choosing each and every decision that I made and
that I was free to do differently if I wished. That nothing was controlling me
to do a certain things and that my decisions were completely free. It wasn’t
until reading and discussing this topic that I really thought about what I
believed and began to question what my previous beliefs had been and what might
be the actual cause to my actions. Many different philosophers have argued a
wide variety of viewpoints on the topic of free will. One of these viewpoints
is called determinism. Which argues that no actions are free by stating; that actions
are free when they are uncaused, and that all actions are caused, therefore no
actions are free. This is to say simply that every decision an individual makes
is predetermined, and was directly caused by something else. And essentially
that an individual’s future is completely decided and cannot be avoided. On the
opposite side of this argument there is the idea that humans contain a “special
sauce” or they are able to defy this idea of cause and effect and make
decisions independently of any causes. This idea supports that there are
transient, or natural causes, which is such that every event has a cause. And
then there are immanent, or agent causes that defy natural causes and they
incorporate this idea of human decisions. There are also other viewpoints in
between these two extremes that include compatibilist view point that states
that free will and determinism can coexist.
After all the readings and discussion I have
come to believe that this idea of compatiblism is what truly accounts for our
actions. I believe that our choices are very much caused in the sense that
there are circumstances that led to the decisions made. But the decision itself
is very much up to the individual making the decision. The way I see it is like
a pathway that at one point forks into two different paths, and the way to go
is chosen by the traveler, and further along the path that they chose is
another fork. The path that the traveler now decides to take was caused by the
previous choice and if they had decided differently at the first fork they
might not have to make this decision now. And again after they choose a second path
they come to another fork and this third decision was caused by the last two,
and if they had decided differently at either previous fork the decision now
might be different. So our choices are cause by previous decisions in the sense
that they lead us to different circumstances that would be different if we had
decided differently, but each choice we make is not forced by previous causes. Take
for example this blog post, the decision to write it was caused by many
different things, or forks in the path, and
each of those things was caused by others, like me choosing to come to Hendrix,
choosing to take this class, choosing to come to class the day the blog was
talked about, my nature to do my homework. All these things caused me to write
this post, and without these causes I wouldn’t be writing this post, but the
actual decision is of my own free will. I could have, despite all these causes,
chose to not write it and get a zero for it on my grade. Therefore I believe
that we are free to choose to do what we want but the options we have to choose
from are caused.
Sunday, September 9, 2012
Personal Testimony
In Hume’s argument, "Of Miracles", he
begins by addressing the function of evidence in supporting the particular
claim of a miracle, defining miracle as a violation of natural laws with the
interference of a holy power. The weight of the evidence determines which of
the claims about the miracle we choose to accept and which we choose to reject.
He regards human testimony as sufficient evidence with, “no species of reasoning more common, more useful,
and even necessary to human life”, establishing acceptable evidence for the
support of miracles. The argument against the occurrence of miracles, however, also
consists of human testimony by being based on the Laws of Nature, which draw
evidence from human experience. The evidence against the incident of a miracle,
then, is most likely to outweigh the evidence for a miraculous happening simply
because the Laws of Nature are founded on an incomparable amount of human
experience and a miracle is usually supported with only a single experience. What
then do we do with testimonies of human witnesses? Does a Witness’s experience
of a miraculous event ever outweigh the ancient laws of nature?
While
the reasonable and sensible side of me wants accept and support this argument I
am torn by the first hand account of witnessing a ghost sighting. Yes it’s true
I have, with my own two eyes, seen a ghost. Not just any ghost but the ghost of
my grandfather Gene. I will be the first to admit that this claim sounds
completely ridiculous, but it was the most amazing moment of wonder, fear, and
belief that I have ever experienced. Although my grandfather was not risen from
the dead, his human form appeared to me, as if he was flesh and blood standing
in my home.
Of course Hume would refute my claim by
questioning my reliability as a witness. I was an imaginative child with a, to
say the very least, odd sense of reality and I was going through the traumatic
event of losing a loved one in my young life. This doesn’t account for the
memory that has stayed with me for over fourteen years and seems to me as if it
only happened yesterday. He may argue that I am working towards some personal
holy campaign, using the supernatural as a force to gain followers. I am not a
religious person though; I have no ulterior religious motives in telling you of
my ghost experience. He may also argue that I have a tendency to believe in the
unbelievable. I do not have a disposition towards believing in the supernatural
though; I have always been taught to question the unknown. He may blame you,
the audience, for being so entrapped by my story you have let your skepticism
guard down and believe my story without proper scrutiny. Please by all means
scrutinize this story as much as you possibly can.
Obviously
I am not the only witness in the world that would argue their claim of a
miracle to no end. When someone has experienced something that has made such an
impression it is virtually impossible to tell him or her otherwise. Hume’s reasoning
of the weight of evidence and the importance of human experience in justifying
or disproving a claim is sound reasoning. While this argument is a strong one
for developing a belief about a miraculous occurrence it does not necessarily
bring us to the truth of these events.
Can We Give Singular Credit?
Sir Thomas Aquinas argues that “Everything in nature
is directed to its goal by someone with understanding, and this we call
god”. He supported his argument
with five premises. His argument is mostly valid and sound, however his second
premise, the nature of causation does not give way to the possibility of two
mutual causes to one event.
As
we discussed the existence of God in class I couldn’t help but question how we
could assume such singularity. In
nature we can notice that a hurricane is caused by more than one factor. The water temperature, wind patterns
and many other things must provide an ideal environment for the hurricanes
formation.
We
as human beings cannot reproduce (the very base to our existence on earth)
without two parts… a sperm and an egg.
So is it a jump in logic to assume that there is a single “First
Cause”.
Considering
the vague objection I am making would quickly be argued through the very
definition of God, as an all knowing, “first cause” accredits him as a single
creator.
As
many ideas that arise have already been thought of, I am sure that this one is
not special but I can’t help but wonder…
If our
scientific method is leading us to truths and the many theories concerning the
origin of the earth have merit, and yet a significant percentage of the human
populations believes in a higher power, God, Creator. Can both these viewpoints not coincide to explain “the
Beginning”?
Some
specific primary texts may be considered falsified in this attempt… raising
hairs… but could god have cofounded our world while still maintain the reputation
as all knowing, all good, and all powerful? I believe he can.
The Importance of Definition
In philosophy, things can often get
messy, as finding answers is never completely clear cut or simple. An important
step in setting out to understand someone else’s argument or formulate your own
is to define the terms used. While many times the words being used are not
uncommon, like the word “beauty” or “truth”, the way the author means them does
not always match up with the conventional definition. One person’s concept of
what is beautiful is not necessarily the same as another’s. The fact that I
like Dvorak does not make him universally appealing, just as my aversion for
Wagner does not makes him unappealing to everyone. Such subjectivity is equally applicable to
definitions. The three statements that Mackie lays out – that God is
all-powerful, all good, and the fact that evil exists– pose a logical problem
when put together. However, each one can be reevaluated by focusing on the key
word, “omnipotent”, “good”, and “evil”, as well as the concept of God.
We see the challenge of defining
things in the dialogue between Socrates and Euthyphro - Socrates repeatedly
asks Euthyphro to tell him what piety is, and each time he finds holes in the
logic presented to him until Euthyphro gets angry that the arguments seem “to
move about instead of staying put”.
Finding the perfect combination of words to describe the concept of
another is a hard enough task, and in philosophy it is important to remember
that the definition the philosopher had in mind is almost never the same as
what you yourself think. Looking at the
concept of goodness, vague terms with positive connotations come to mind.
“Good” is one of the more primary words – when I try to find a describe it the
first thing that comes to mind is merely “not bad”, which isn’t much better. Thinking about what is evil is a little more
fruitful, I unhelpfully think of “not good”, but also “bad, harmful, a cause of
hurt and pain”. Recognizing whether something is good or bad is somewhat of an
easier task on a basic level, we humans automatically sort everything into
categories. Going with the assumption that God is all good, we now can attach
another definition to each, so what is good is “of God”, while what is evil is
“not of God”. It is important to make sure that the intended definition is
understood. While “goodness” is an easier word, the term “God” is not.
Kyle already talked a little about
altering the fixed view of what God is. Christianity thinks of God as an
anthropomorphic figure who loves but judges all humans at death. If you
redefine God as something other than this narrow concept, then you can by-step
the whole conundrum Mackie sets out for us. For example, if “God” was actually “the
gods”, as is the case with a polytheistic belief system, then there would be no
problem accepting that fact that they were omnipotent and that evil existed, as
it could easily be explained that the gods have conflicting interests. The fact
that God is a like a human with motivations and consciousness is another
debatable point. Pantheists characterize
God not as a figure, but as the sum of everything in the world, and so “God” is
still omnipotent, because nothing exists outside of it; the concept of being
good is not applicable because God is no longer a separate entity. Looking at each part of the apparent problem can
provide enough questions and discussions without even exploring the main
purpose of the argument, but can help understand the proposed solution in the
long run.
Hume's Of Miracles
In class on Friday, we defined a
miracle as a violation of the laws of nature. For a miracle to exist, it must
require a supernatural power to intervene and violate some natural law. In
general, miracles are associated with God as his omnipotence is the explanation
for the violation of accepted and proven natural laws. So it is easy for those
who believe in an all-powerful God to accept miracles as their God’s works. But
for those who question or do not believe in God, miracles remain without
sufficient explanation. Because the existence of miracles goes back always to
the existence of God, it is one that has been and will be disputed forever.
In “Of
Miracles”, Hume writes his essay on miracles in such a way that he is able to
outline each of the arguments pertaining to miracles and if or how they exist. In
reading about David Hume, I was primarily informed that he was atheist and a
skeptic and many of his famous works reflected those views. However, while
reading this particular essay on miracles, I found it very unapparent that he
so adamantly believed that God did not exist; instead he simply outlined each
side of the argument of the existence of miracles.
Hume leaves
the question up to the individual to decide whether the miracle did or did not
happen. He allows us each to decide which sounds more miraculous: the miracle
or the falseness of the testimony of the miracle. I very much enjoyed reading
his response to miracles as it provides many different trains of thought useful
when personally deciding whether miracles do or do not exist. And not being
much of a natural philosopher, this approach is especially useful to me.
It was
interesting to me too that he mentions how miracles that were recorded in
biblical times were those coming from people who are “barbarous” and that it is
no wonder that miracles such as those do not happen much in modern times; Hume
says that it is not only a modern concept to lie. And when we look at miracles
in this sense, it seems sort of surprising to me that such debate has been
going on for so long about whether miracles exist or not because all humans
know how easy and appealing it is to lie for whatever reasons. It is easy to
detect his skepticism throughout his essay and especially when he discusses the
credibility of the testimonies of various miracles. The first point he makes in
the second section of his article is that in all of history, there is no
miracle that has been witnessed and recorded by a reliable and sufficient
amount of men such that all of our doubts about their credibility are retracted.
Each of the
points that Hume makes in his essay leaves the question of miracles’ existence
open-ended and for the individuals to decide for themselves, making it a
wonderful starting point for forming and opinion and creating an argument on
the topic.
Subscribe to:
Posts (Atom)